Place and Expression

This is a response I gave to a paper entitled ‘Leibniz on Place’ by Jen Nguyen at DePaul’s philosophy graduate conference yesterday, 2.11.2017.

Nguyen’s paper raises a fascinating series of issues in the context of Leibniz’s metaphysics, which to my mind come down to this central question: where is a place? In some ways, as she notes, Leibniz’s view on place is commonsensical enough: a place will turn out to be a point of view on the world; this is its intrinsic determination, as opposed to the purely extrinsic or formal definition, according to which a place is a set of coordinates in abstract three-dimensional space. And if this squares with common sense, it’s due to a strange sort of phenomenological intuition, rather like how, to borrow from Wilfrid Sellars’ terminology, we sense an incompleteness in the ‘scientific image’ of the world and supplement it with the ‘manifest image’. We want to say: no, this place, this room, is not defined by the amount of space, the quantitative distance between the walls, the placement of the windows, the positions of these tables and chairs; rather it is a matter of the way we perceive it, what it opens up for us, how we are determined within it, a question of perspective and orientation, affect and delimitation: it is how we express it.

But if things get off to a sensible enough start, they also get weird very quickly. Leibniz never leaves a thought half developed; he will always follow it to the end, however unintuitive and bizarre. For, as Nguyen argues, the central question here becomes: what are the metaphysical foundations of place? And to answer this, it won’t be enough to jettison the definition of place as a local configuration of abstract space for being merely extrinsic. We need an intrinsic, genetic and concrete definition. Leibniz always begins so innocently; we start by making a true claim. ‘You are here today.’ True. Now we ask: what is the basis, the ground for the truth of this claim? And Leibniz responds: it is in the nature of the things themselves. And this because the alternative verges on the incomprehensible: we would claim that it is true that you are here, but somehow this truth would have nothing to do with your nature or the nature of this place; that seems absurd. But if Leibniz says that true predication is based in the nature of the subject, then place becomes a particularly odd focal point through which to, if you like, test his metaphysics: for if I say, truly, that ‘you are here’, then ‘here’ becomes one of your true attributes. So that ‘crossing the Rubicon’ is a true attribute of Caesar; but, moreover, the Rubicon does not exist at all outside true attributions like this, in which it constitutes a real site for a subject’s becoming.

In fact, all attributes are evental, they involve durations and passages. This is why the standard critique of the ‘metaphysics of substance’ misses Leibniz and, incidentally, Spinoza. For Spinoza and Leibniz converge here, by way of inverted philosophical movements. According to Spinoza, there is an absolutely infinite single substance; according to Leibniz, there is an absolute infinity of distinct substances. Could they be more apparently opposed to one another? Spinoza says: the characteristics of an individual mode are all extrinsic, there are no essential qualities (those all belong to substance); Leibniz says: every individual substance’s characteristics are intrinsic, there are no accidental qualities. But something odd happens here; where there is no line any longer separating an individual’s essential from accidental, or intrinsic from extrinsic properties – a dialectic commences that implicates the whole world in each of its parts and vice versa, where monism and monadology ceaselessly pass over into one another by means of the category of expression; and Nguyen’s emphasis on the significance of this category, expression, is an aspect of her paper I appreciate greatly. For Spinoza, there is only one substance, but it only exists as expressed in its modes; for Leibniz, there is only the world, but it is made up exclusively of the monads that express it. For both, individuals are expressive of the whole, and their attributes and characteristics are all relational.

What distinguishes monads—what individuates one—is nothing other than its singular difference, its unique point of view on one and the same world. But each monad in fact expresses the whole world, everything at once. In what, then, does this difference consist? As with most things in Leibniz, it is a matter of ratio. If I perceive or express the entire world as a whole, it’s obviously not the case that I perceive or express everything clearly. In fact, the vast majority of what I perceive remains totally obscure to me. One of Leibniz’s great lessons is that these obscure perceptions are not nothing; those of my perceptions that are unconscious or obscure are still real differences that make a difference. Imagine the contrary: that the only differences that make a difference are those that are clearly expressed in consciousness, as if the world ceased to exist when I don’t look at it. Leibniz’s innovation is to suggest that when we don’t express part of the world clearly, we still always do so obscurely. Nguyen cites Leibniz in the Discourse: every substance “expresses, however confusedly, everything that happens in the universe, past, present, and future.” (Discourse on Metaphysics, §9) My unique difference, then, my singularity or individuation, is the particular ratio of clarity and obscurity with which I express the world as a whole. And what I express or perceive clearly is a matter of my body, my bodily relations of proximity and distance, the intensity and distinctness of what strikes me in these embodied situations.

So let’s go back to the river Rubicon. It is the locus or site of a crossing, an evental attribute which is essential to Caesar. It is a place, but not indifferently or abstractly, as a piece of three-dimensional space (as in the model of Newton’s space as absolute container). Rather, if it is a place, it is because it is where an event transpires, in the strange perfect future anterior mood of all truths understood by God: Caesar will always have crossed the Rubicon. So where is it? In some way, since the claim is analytically true, we have to say that it’s not just the event of crossing it but the river Rubicon itself that is virtually contained in the complete concept of Caesar. But not just Caesar: as a real place where events transpire, it is contained no less in the complete concepts of all those who ever will have crossed it, bathed in it, drank from it, even heard about it or just reflected on it. To follow Nguyen’s example from Moby Dick, even falling silent in the cathedral is an event, a manner in which the place of the cathedral expresses itself in the conduct of the wayward sailors. But since each monad expresses the whole world, we have to go with Leibniz to the limit: the Rubicon is part of the complete concept of every single person who ever will have been part of the world; it’s just that, for the most part, its mode of inclusion in all these minds is very obscure and minimal, a difference that makes almost no difference, where the difference made is unassignably small or imperceptible.

We can thus say that a place just is the spatiotemporal locus of a becoming or an event, on which each monad has a unique perspective or point of view, a unique distribution of expressive clarity and obscurity. It is a part of the world in which all singularities become what they are. A place exists only in the perception of a monad, or as a virtual part of a complete concept, but it is also more than this, since no single concept or mind expresses it in the full richness of its real articulation; when the world just is the totality of monads that are points of view on it, each finite place becomes an infinity mirror, a site of infinite expression. And for each place the question is then transformed: how can we express it more clearly, how do we diminish the proportional obscurity of our understanding, the passivity of our bodies and minds? How do we become active—not in general, not indifferently, but concretely and determinately active in each particular place? How do we open ourselves to the texture and rhythm of a place? Or, under what conditions does a place enter into its own becoming, which is expressed in and through us? These are the kinds of questions that Nguyen’s paper raises, and I am grateful for the opportunity to think them together with you that she has provided us here today.

Advertisements

3 thoughts on “Place and Expression”

  1. Hey Gil, Rob here! Really enjoyed this. So I’m going to desecrate your new blog with a question.

    Toward the end you say something a bit paradoxical–that, on the one hand, place just is a determination of the complete concepts of the various monads. On the other hand, place is something more than the monads, because those monads need to strive to increase the clarity of the expression of the place in their own concepts. So prior to this clarification, place is both there and not there. This seems like a really rich paradox, and I think it hits on something I really like about the German Idealists and Heidegger: basically, their idealism. What I mean is their recognition, respectively, of the codependence of subject and substance or being and its “there” (Dasein/world/whatever). As I understand it, this codependence rests on the fact that being only ever takes intelligible, determinate form, for a knowing subject of determinate intelligence. In other words, being is being only insofar as it is disclosed in a determinate way, and the determinacy depends on the structure of the historical, determinate dative of disclosure. So, if so far so good, one thing I puzzle over is this: Dasein and being, or subject and substance, are both supposed to be more than each other. That is, they are not just features of the same thing. There is always more being to be disclosed, or (maybe…) more substance to be made determinate and recollected. But if the two sides depend on one another, how can the exceed one another? In other words, where is being “before” disclosure? Where is substance before it is sublated into the life of spirit? And for Leibniz, where is place when it is still “obscure”?

    (Interestingly, I’m not sure whether the question works from the flipside: where is dasein before the disclosure of being, where is the subject before its sublation into spirit, because dasein already have the structure of world and spirit, and grow in that structure to the extent that they achieve the disclosure of (“consume?”!) being. )

    Anyway, that was a lot. But I wonder what you think about what Leibniz (or any of the above) would say about the “where” of place/spirit/being prior to its manifestation to monad/spirit/dasein?

    Like

    1. Hey Rob! Good to hear from you.

      1. I think that, on the first point, Leibniz is actually up to something a bit different than the German idealists + Heidegger. If we assume that there exists some region of being or aspect of reality which no monad ever clearly expresses, some place in the world that is only ever expressed very obscurely, we would not thereby be permitted to say that it does not exist. So in your formulation: that, prior to clear expression in some monad, the place is ‘both there and not there’ – I think there are reasons to read Leibniz as saying, in fact, that it always was there. If this isn’t materialism, contra idealism, perhaps it’s still some kind of realism. This because even if some part of the world is not clearly expressed as such, it still has determinate effects, at the level of how it obscurely affects minds. So while I agree that being only ever takes intelligible form on condition that some mind that clearly expresses it, I would argue that it can take determinate form without this condition being necessary. To answer your question directly, unthought being is still determinate enough to make a difference even if it is never disclosed as such (although I am somewhat uncomfortable with that kind of Heideggerian formulation). Finally I might say that your characterization of ‘codependence of subject and substance’ is probably true for the post-Kantian German idealists (Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel, and I would think for Heidegger too, but maybe not for Kant, who always insisted that transcendental idealism also necessarily involves empirical realism.

      2. I quite like your recognition of the doubly excessive character of, let’s call it material being or substance on the one hand, and subjective or monadic expressivity on the other. So we have: the world/substance qua obscure exceeds its clear expression in minds; minds qua expressive agency exceed the simple fact of substantial existence. I’d also say that, for Leibniz, the excess on both sides is inexhaustible in principle: monads can always become more active, the world can always be more clearly expressed. Things look a little different in Spinoza; Ethics II P7 (‘The order and connection of ideas is the same as the order and connection of things’) entails that, strictly speaking, there is nothing more or excessive on either side of the thought/extension divide. The whole question of how precisely to parse the difference between the attributes (defined as ‘that which the intellect perceives as constituting the essence of a substance’) is a controversial topic (e.g.: is this phrasing supposed to mean that the difference is merely epistemic? or does the intellect grasp some real distinction here? or again, keeping in mind Spinoza’s typology of knowledges, which kind is at work in this definition?). I think we end up having to say both: a. that there is no more reality, perfection, being, existence, force, power, etc. in extension as opposed to thought, or vice versa; and b. that thought and extension, as attributes or essential determinations of substance, are nevertheless strictly irreducible to one another. This irreducibility of thought and extension may be close enough to what you mean by ‘exceeding one another’, but I can equally imagine it not being satisfying in this regard.

      Like

Leave a Reply

Fill in your details below or click an icon to log in:

WordPress.com Logo

You are commenting using your WordPress.com account. Log Out / Change )

Twitter picture

You are commenting using your Twitter account. Log Out / Change )

Facebook photo

You are commenting using your Facebook account. Log Out / Change )

Google+ photo

You are commenting using your Google+ account. Log Out / Change )

Connecting to %s